Initially find to be puzzling, or even an
egregious affront to common sense. Plato assumes, following Parmenides, that
what is real may be thought and what is thought may be said. In other words,
reality may be known through rational inquiry or thinking and the resultant
thoughts may be communicated propositionally. But how do linguistically
expressed judgments convey truths about non-linguistic realities?
Forms
as class concepts.
If A is a certain woman and B is a certain
statue and both “A is beautiful” and “B is beautiful” are true statements, one
might be tempted to think of the woman and the statue as participating in or sharing some
common property–beauty, despite their being otherwise quite different. This is
the way Plato thinks, and he calls the common property ‘beauty itself,’ as
distinct from the particular beauty of either woman or statue (unfortunately,
translators often feel compelled to turn Plato’s ‘beauty itself’ into “ideal
beauty” or “absolute beauty”). How can we intelligently say that some
particular objects are beautiful unless we have a prior acquaintance
with beauty itself, so that we can identify it in those objects? Knowledge of
‘the beautiful itself’ is a prerequisite for knowing whether ‘A is beautiful’
or ‘B is beautiful’ are true statements.
Philosophers talk of conceptual or logical priority as distinct from temporal priority, and this is the
sort of firstness at issue here. If an understanding of x is necessary
for an understanding of y, then x is conceptually or logically
prior to y. It would seem that, if we are to understand what we are
saying when we say ‘This woman is beautiful,’ we must understand what
‘beautiful’ means. Nor can we know whether that or any other statement is true
(i.e., is an item of knowledge)
unless we understood what the statement means. What then is the status of all
those statements, constituting the vast majority of our assertions, which we
make before we have established a clear understanding of the terms the
statements contain? Plato would say that they must only be opinions, since they clearly cannot be
instances of knowledge.
Forms
as standards.
Neither the woman nor the statue of our
example, nor any other concrete sensible object, is perfectly beautiful, for
each of these objects is many things (for example, woman, red-headed, slim,
graceful, with a wart on her left hand, etc.) and not just this one
thing–beautiful. Only “the beautiful itself” is just beauty uncompounded with
any other properties. The beautiful woman “participates in” or “shares” this
beauty with all other beautiful things, but both she and all those other things
can only be beautiful in certain respects and to a certain degree. The
concept of beauty, or what Plato calls “the beautiful itself” or “Beauty,”
provides a standard with which
to judge individual objects as being more or less beautiful. Because they are
the patterns or ideal models to which we compare individual things or actions
in order to determine how beautiful, just, or whatever, they are, he
also refers to them as ‘Forms’
or ‘Ideas.’ For this reason,
Plato’s view has been called idealism.
Our
knowledge of Forms.
It is clear that we cannot apprehend Forms
by our senses. We see the beautiful person, but beauty itself is not something
we can see or hear. We would say that we ‘have an idea’ or ‘have a concept’ of
beauty; Plato writes of apprehending Forms with ‘the mind’ or ‘the eye of the
soul’ rather than with the senses. We do hear beautiful pieces of music and see
beautiful objects, but Plato’s point is that we are able to do so only because
we have some idea of what beauty itself is. Even if hearing a sound is entirely
an affair of the sense organs, hearing that sound as beautiful is to
mentally classify it as having satisfied those ideal conditions, which would be
specified in a definition of “beauty.” Some would say that our concepts are
constructed by the mind by a process of selective abstraction from sensible
experience–that, in effect, we make our ideas. This view has sometimes been
called nominalism, because concepts are nothing more than names
by which we conventionally designate certain sensible properties or patterns of
sensible properties. Plato does not agree with this view. He thinks that our
ideas are not like artefacts, but rather like perceptions. That is, just as
visual perceptions are of objects, which exist outside us, our concepts are
mental perceptions of non-sensible realities which likewise exist independently
of us. This view has sometimes been called realism, because it takes mental
objects to be objectively real.
Thinking this way, it makes perfectly good
sense to say that ‘Beauty really exists’ and that it will be whatever it is
regardless of how you or I may think of it. Plato thinks that if Beauty and
Justice were only names and not realities then all our aesthetic and moral
judgments would only express conventional prejudices and that none of them
could be true. How would this consequence follow? Because, as Parmenides had
argued, knowledge is apprehension of what really is. If ‘beauty’ or ‘justice’
are not realities, then statements such as “Symmetry is beautiful” and “Paying
debts is just” couldn’t be evaluated as either true or false, because there
would be no non-arbitrary, natural, standard, meaning of ‘beautiful’ or ‘just.’
Further, there is an obvious difference between perception and knowledge.
Knowledge is mental or conceptual, not sensible, experience. If knowledge is
the correct apprehension of what truly exits, and if Forms did not exist, there
would not be anything to know, for the only existing objects would be sensible,
rather than conceivable, realities.
Reality.
If Plato is right, we are not entitled to
think of reality in the conventional commonsense way, that is, to assume that
that which is sensible is most real. That which really exists is to be
apprehended only through thinking–by constructing and testing theories. Sensible
objects could not possibly be real; they could at best be “copies” or “images” (as Plato calls them) of underlying realities which can be
thought about but which cannot be perceived. In short, what we usually call
“the real world” is not that at all, but is rather just a world of appearance or seeming. Only the Forms really exist, for they are the “causes”
(in the sense of archetypal standards) of whatever intelligible properties are
discernible in those sensible things, which seem to be most real. If we don’t
know what beauty, or equality, or justice is ideally, how can we recognize
particular instances of these?
Interestingly, this means that the examples
we began by considering–statements such as “This woman is beautiful”–cannot
ever be cases of knowledge, because the subject expression designates a
sensible, rather than an intelligible, object. We could never be certain of
more than that “This woman seems beautiful,” because this opinion relies
on ever changing and always incomplete observational evidence. The only
statements which could express genuine knowledge would be those whose subject
terms, as well as their predicate terms, designated Forms. In logical jargon,
knowledge can be expressed only in universal propositions, not in singular
propositions (propositions whose subject refers to some particular thing rather
than to a Form). Scientific statements, as well as the definitions of virtues
sought by Socrates in Plato’s dialogues, are not about particular facts or
objects but about universals.
No comments:
Post a Comment